Thursday, October 11, 2012

Kantorowicz Review


Review- Ernst H. Kantorowicz. The King’s Two Bodies with a New Preface by William Chester Jordan. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.
                Kantorowicz’s The King’s Two Bodies has entered the annals of medieval history in particular, and history in general. William Chester Jordan, in the preface to this work, states that, even though the first draft of The King’s Two Bodies dates to 1955, the work is still “indispensable for all investigations of staatstheorie and political theology” (p.xiv), and furthermore, the work “remains indeed, a wonderfully exciting and constantly rewarding book” (p.xv). On the one hand, Kantorowicz’s perspective, by his own admission (p.xix), is narrow: he focuses on the concept of the duality of the king as an institution and a person (Introduction). On the other hand, the conclusions cannot possibly limit themselves to this duality. That is, the notion of The King’s Two Bodies become as much historical practice and behavior as it is an ideology.
                Kantorowicz begins his work with a conundrum that was posed by a legal case: in 1715, King George III wished to hold some royal land as private property. Parliament denied the king’s request. For them, the King was legally immortal, always and permanently King. And yet, the person of the king is mortal (p.4-5). It is this idea of the persona mixta, of the immortal King and mortal king that Kantorowicz investigates.
                Kantorowicz finds the ultimate expression of the King’s two bodies in the legal writings of the Tudor lawyers. In a series of legal cases, the lawyers of the Tudor period articulated the notion that the individual, once king, was endowed with the spirit of the office, which spirit migrated from one body politic to another freely upon the death of a monarch. The execution of Charles I in 1642 confirmed that this body politic, the idea of the immortal King, needed not be a single person: after the death of Charles, the King resided in Parliament. From these anecdotes, Kantorowicz identifies a crucial paradigm: the individual king, like Christ, was endowed with a mortal essence as well as an immortal one, even if this particular aspect is not stated explicitly (Chapter 1).
                Kantorowicz sees the development of the King’s two bodies in the dialogues between church and state. The crucial point that Kantorowicz identifies is that the King’s two bodies arises from the progressive secularization of the Church and its opposite, the sanctification of the temporal powers of the state. The first development is the idea that the king is a persona mixta, like Christ, a mediator between heaven and earth. The bishops, Kantorowicz state, are also personae mixtae in that same way. In the works of the Anonymous Norman, both king and bishop are both expressions of the incarnation of Christ on earth. The one caveat is that the Anonymous Norman, Kantorowicz argues is not a part of his time, but the representation of antiquated ideologies (chapter 3).
                The rediscovery of the Roman legal tradition changes the ideological battlefields (Chapter 4).  From purely rhetorical concepts, royal and papal lawyers both considered the legal implications of the persona mixta. The king changes from vicarius Christi and thus mediator between heaven and earth, to the mediator between natural or divine law, and equity or temporal law. The king derived his former power from his right to legislate, given by the lex regia, and his duty to obey, as expressed in the lex digna. The conundrum of the king as supreme legislator and yet subject to his own laws brought about a crucial development: Bracton distinguished between the temporary  ties that binds him to his subjects (res privata) and the permanent ties that bind him to his realm (res fisca) (p.165-193). 
                Bracton’s ideas, though centered on England, had echoes in ecclesiastical discourses, which, in turn, are mirrored in secular ideologies (Chapter 5): the abstraction of the realm as patria and organic imagery for the state, with the pope/king as head, and the commonwealth as body (Thomas Aquinas, p.204). Papal lawyers established the pope as the head of the corpus mysticum and the corpus iudicum. The parallel developments stems from the definition of the realm as imperium sacrum, a notion directly borrowed from Roman Law. The anointment and the coronation also increasingly come to mean that the king is married to his commonwealth, which means that the nature of kingship becomes centered on the polity. The reign of Philip IV the Fair takes the imagery even further, the king asks his people to protect the realm, and the dynasty (p.250-267).
                This relationship is not yet complete. In the works of secular theorists like Dubois, the king/head can still die (p.269). It is only with the rediscovery of Aristotelitian notions of infinite continuity and the demonstration that the individual is representative of an eternal genus. From this, Kantorowicz develops the notion of political permanence (chapter 6). All that remains is to apply the same perpetuity to the head. This, Kantorowicz argues, can only be done, once three conditions are met: establishing 1) the perpetuity of the dynasty, 2) the corporate character of the crown, and 3) the immortality of royal dignity.  The first condition is met once the kings remove the necessity for both coronation and election. For instance, Philip III, due to political expediency, becomes king without election and before coronation upon the death of St Louis (p.328). The second is met once the crown is divorced from the person of the king, but not the office. This was achieved when jurists began to blur the distinction between crown and king (p.359-381). Finally, dignitas becomes synonymous with the immortal genus mentioned in chapter 6. As such, royal dignity allows the transference of authority from one dynast to the next, or, from one body politic to another (p.389-449). Dante finishes Kantorowicz’s analysis by establishing the parallel between man and Adam, the archetype of transcendence and human perfection (chapter 8).
                Unlike intellectual historians, Kantorowicz focuses on the evolution of the idea. While the intellectual historian organizes his work by scholars, Kantorowicz organizes the work around the evolution of the concept. As such, humans themselves are only relevant as articulators of the idea, and are not major players.  Thus must one understand the criticism of Schoek that there is “too much crammed in between the covers” (p.xi).
The methodology requires Kantorowicz to focus on the evolution of statements and ideas by equivalency. For example, papal lawyers crafted the notion of corpus mysticum et spirituale, while by equivalency, royal lawyers crafted the notion of corpus morale et politicum. The problem with reasoning by equivalency is that royal lawyers may be responding intellectually to the papal lawyers, at the same time, the question for the necessity of that rhetoric equivalency is relegated to the background: political necessity and context play only a minor role in Kantorowicz’s analysis; statements evolve in the context of the scholastic debates.
                And yet, politics are never truly absent. Kantorowicz’s tour de force lies in his ability to remind the reader constantly of the importance of the historical events. In this study, the reader is constantly reminded of the crucial importance of the Investiture Contest (ca.1050-1180), which acted as the catalyst for the redefinition of papal politics and royal ideologies. Kantorowicz makes only once the statement that “that struggle itself, on the one hand dismantling the secular power of spiritual authority ecclesiastical competency and liturgical affiliation, and, on the other, imperializing the spiritual power, had certainly its share” (p.90). In other words, the rhetorical rapprochement between king and pope is the result of the pressures of a single moment in time.
                The main absentee from Kantorowicz’s analysis is not the lawyer, but the law-code. Indeed, Kantorowicz’s concept of the law seems to encompass only political thinkers and theorists. However, the only laws that Kantorowicz quotes are early-medieval, ancient, or canon, and even then, the Digest of Justinian is preferred to his Novella. The underlying assumption with Kantorowicz’s source use is that the interpretation of lawyers must be reflected somehow in the law codes. Kantorowicz is aware of this objection (p.273), but yet ignores the legal documents coming from the royal chancery. The revolution in law codes and legal collections explode in the twelfth century,[1] and should shed light on the practical implementations of the theological and legal arguments that took place in monasteries and universities. Law Codes would add a layer of analysis to the argument
                Faulting Kantorowicz for limited source use is perhaps not entirely fair to the monumental intellectual labors that went into the synthesis of so many sources, for which he was praised (p.ix). This work is a testament to a method, to the evolution of an idea that provoked radical changes in the understanding of royal monarchy in Europe.

                The subsequent part is not part of the original review, but rather a summary of the class discussion that ensued.
                One aspect of the book I had only implicitly picked up on but not fully articulated was the notion of Geistesgeschichte (loosely translated as the history of the spirit). What is evident from Kantorowicz’s book is the notion of the universal geist or the underlying spirit that qualifies an age. For Kantorowicz, this geist is found primarily in the judicial, theological and literary writings of what he perceives as the elite, that is, Shakespeare, Dante, Aquinas and even the Anonymous Norman. These people all articulate, in their own way, the geist of their age.
                The variations between scholars, though duly noted, are not emphasized. The primary goal of Kantorowicz is then to demonstrate not how each scholar/writer influenced one another, but rather to demonstrate the way in which they are similar, even though each functioned in a different historical context. The implication of this statement, I believe, invalidates my initial criticism that historical context is only latent in Kantorowicz’s work primarily because the geist, for Kantorowicz, functions as a meta-historical variable.
                One point that was raised during our class discussion was whether or not this approach to history was valid. The student objected strongly to Kantorowicz’s methodological axiom, stating that (in the immortal words of Thucydides, “he spoke such things”) “ideas do not simply float around.” That is, there is no geist to speak of. Scholars interact (here perhaps indirectly influenced by the Republic of Letters), scholars talk, scholars respond to historical circumstances.
                Still, one can wonder. Both as a respondent and a presenter at historical conferences, I have had the pleasure (or distasteful surprise) to place and be placed into broad philosophical currents. As the responder, I had the distinct pleasure of arguing that political discourses of the Late-Roman Republic were understood by the presenter as part of the Borderlands theory, even when she never uttered those words. As a presenter, I was told that I was a deconstructionalist, even when I only broached Derrida two years later (and I am still not done…). Does this qualify as geist? Or do methods of thinking simply permeate our lives so much that one can be a deconstructionalist without having ever read anything from Derrida and his associates? If we were to include the historical variable, could we still speak of a geist?


[1] Dominique Barthélémy, The Serf, the Knight and the Historian (Cornell: Ithaca University Press, 2009).